Last semester I tutored the course Probability Modelling with Applications. In this course the main objects of study are probability spaces. A probability space is a triple where:
is a set.
is a
-algebra on
. That is
is a collection of subsets of
such that
and
is closed under set complements and countable unions. The element of
are called events and they are precisely the subsets of
that we can assign probabilities to. We will denote the power set of
by
and hence
.
is a probability measure. That is it is a function
such that
and for all countable collections
of mutually disjoint subsets we have that
.
It’s common for students to find probability spaces, and in particular -algebras, confusing. Unfortunately Vitalli showed that
-algebras can’t be avoided if we want to study probability spaces such as
or an infinite number of coin tosses. One of the main reasons why
-algebras can be so confusing is that it can be very hard to give concrete descriptions of all the elements of a
-algebra.
We often have a collection of subsets of
that we are interested in but this collection fails to be a
-algebra. For example, we might have
and
is the collection of open subsets. In this situation we take our
-algebra
to be
which is the smallest
-algebra containing
. That is
where the above intersection is taken over all -algebras
that contain
. In this setting we will say that
generates
. When we have such a collection of generators, we might have an idea for what probability we would like to assign to sets in
. That is we have a function
and we want to extend this function to create a probability measure
. A famous theorem due to Caratheodory shows that we can do this in many cases.
An interesting question is whether the extension is unique. That is does there exists a probability measure
on
such that
but
? The following theorem gives a criterion that guarantees no such
exists.
Theorem: Let be a set and let
be a collection of subsets of
that is closed under finite intersections. Then if
are two probability measures such that
, then
.
The above theorem is very useful for two reasons. Firstly it can be combined with Caratheodory’s extension theorem to uniquely define probability measures on a -algebra by specifying the values on a collection of simple subsets
. Secondly if we ever want to show that two probability measures are equal, the above theorem tells us we can reduce the problem to checking equality on the simpler subsets in
.
The condition that must be closed under finite intersections is somewhat intuitive. Suppose we had
but
. We will however have
and thus we might be able to find two probability measure
such that
and
but
. The following counterexample shows that this intuition is indeed well-founded.
When looking for examples and counterexamples, it’s good to try to keep things as simple as possible. With that in mind we will try to find a counterexample when is finite set with as few elements as possible and
is equal to the powerset of
. In this setting, a probability measure
can be defined by specifying the values
for each
.
We will now try to find a counterexample when is as small as possible. Unfortunately we won’t be able find a counterexample when
only contains one or two elements. This is because we want to find
such that
is not equal to
or
.
Thus we will start out search with a three element set . Up to relabelling the elements of
, the only interesting choice we have for
is
. This has a chance of working since
is not closed under intersection. However any probability measure
on
must satisfy the equations
-
,
,
.
Thus ,
and
. Thus
is determined by its values on
and
.
However, a four element set is sufficient for our counter example! We can let
. Then
and we can define
by
,
,
and
.
,
,
and
.
Clearly however
and
. Thus we have our counterexample! In general for any
we can define the probability measure
. The measure
is not equal to
but agrees with
on
. In general, if we have two probability measures that agree on
but not on
then we can produce uncountably many such measures by taking convex combinations as done above.