The following post is based on a talk I gave at the 2022 Stanford statistics retreat. The talk was titled “Another non-measurable monster”.

The material was based on the discussion and references given in this stackexchange post. The title is a reference to a Halloween lecture on measurability given by Professor Persi Diaconis.
What’s scarier than a non-measurable set?
Making every set measurable. Or rather one particular consequence of making every set measurable.
In my talk, I argued that if you make every set measurable, then there exists a set and an equivalence relation
on
such that
. That is, the set
has strictly smaller cardinality than the set of equivalence classes
. The contradictory nature of this statement is illustrated in the picture below

To make sense of this we’ll first have to be a bit more precise about what we mean by cardinality.
What do we mean by bigger and smaller?
Let and
be two sets. We say that
and
have the same cardinality and write
if there exists a bijection function
. We can think of the function
as a way of pairing each element of
with a unique element of
such that every element of
is paired with an element of
.
We next want to define which means
has cardinality at most the cardinality of
. There are two reasonable ways in which we could try to define this relationship
- We could say
means that there exists an injective function
.
- Alternatively, we could
means that there exists a surjective function
.
Definitions 1 and 2 say similar things and, in the presence of the axiom of choice, they are equivalent. Since we are going to be making every set measurable in this talk, we won’t be assuming the axiom of choice. Definitions 1 and 2 are thus no longer equivalent and we have a decision to make. We will use definition . in this talk. For justification, note that definition 1 implies that there exists a subset such that
. We simply take
to be the range of
. This is a desirable property of the relation
and it’s not clear how this could be done using definition 2.
Infinite binary sequences
It’s time to introduce the set and the equivalence relation we will be working with. The set
is the set
the set of all function
. We can think of each elements
as an infinite sequence of zeros and ones stretching off in both directions. For example
.
But this analogy hides something important. Each has a “middle” which is the point
. For instance, the two sequences below look the same but when we make
bold we see that they are different.
,
.
The equivalence relation on
can be thought of as forgetting the location
. More formally we have
if and only if there exists
such that
for all
. That is, if we shift the sequence
by
we get the sequence
. We will use
to denote the equivalence class of
and
for the set of all equivalences classes.
Some probability
Associated with the space are functions
, one for each integer
. These functions simply evaluate
at
. That is
. A probabilist or statistician would think of
as reporting the result of one of infinitely many independent coin tosses. Normally to make this formal we would have to first define a
-algebra on
and then define a probability on this
-algebra. Today we’re working in a world where every set is measurable and so don’t have to worry about
-algebras. Indeed we have the following result:
(Solovay, 1970)1 There exists a model of the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms of set theory such that there exists a probability defined on all subsets of
such that
are i.i.d.
.
This result is saying that there is world in which, other than the axiom of choice, all the regular axioms of set theory holds. And in this world, we can assign a probability to every subset in a way so that the events
are all independent and have probability
. It’s important to note that this is a true countably additive probability and we can apply all our familiar probability results to
. We are now ready to state and prove the spooky result claimed at the start of this talk.
Proposition: Given the existence of such a probability ,
.
Proof: Let be any function. To show that
we need to show that
is not injective. To do this, we’ll first define another function
given by
. That is,
first maps
to
‘s equivalence class and then applies
to this equivalence class. This is illustrated below.

We will show that is almost surely constant with respect to
. That is, there exists
such that
. Each equivalence class
is finite or countable and thus has probability zero under
. This means that if
is almost surely constant, then
cannot be injective and must map multiple (in fact infinitely many) equivalence classes to
.
It thus remains to show that is almost surely constant. To do this we will introduce a third function
. The map
is simply the shift map and is given by
. Note that
and
are in the same equivalence class for every
. Thus, the map
satisfies
. That is
is
-invariant.
The map is ergodic. This means that if
satisfies
, then
equals
or
. For example if
is the event that
appears at some point in
, then
and
. Likewise if
is the event that the relative frequency of heads converges to a number strictly greater than
, then
and
. The general claim that all
-invariant events have probability
or
can be proved using the independence of
.
For each , define an event
by
. Since
is
-invariant we have that
. Thus,
or
. This gives us a function
given by
. Note that for every
,
. This is because if
, then
, by definition of
. Likewise if
, then
and hence
. Thus, in both cases,
.
Since is a probability measure, we can conclude that
.
Thus, map
to
with probability one. Showing that
is almost surely constant and hence that
is not injective.
There’s a catch!
So we have proved that there cannot be an injective map . Does this mean we have proved
? Technically no. We have proved the negation of
which does not imply
. To argue that
we need to produce a map
that is injective. Surprising this is possible and not too difficult. The idea is to find a map
such that
implies that
. This can be done by somehow encoding in
where the centre of
is.
A simpler proof and other examples
Our proof was nice because we explicitly calculated the value where
sent almost all of
. We could have been less explicit and simply noted that the function
was measurable with respect to the invariant
-algebra of
and hence almost surely constant by the ergodicity of
.
This quicker proof allows us to generalise our “spooky result” to other sets. Below are two examples where
- Fix
and define
if and only if
for some
.
if and only if
.
A similar argument can be used to show that in Solovay’s world . The exact same argument follows from the ergodicity of the corresponding actions on
under the uniform measure.
Three takeaways
I hope you agree that this example is good fun and surprising. I’d like to end with some remarks.
- The first remark is some mathematical context. This argument given today is linked to some interesting mathematics called descriptive set theory. This field studies the properties of well behaved subsets (such as Borel subsets) of topological spaces. Descriptive set theory incorporates logic, topology and ergodic theory. I don’t know much about the field but in Persi’s Halloween talk he said that one “monster” was that few people are interested in the subject.
- The next remark is a better way to think about our “spooky result”. The result is really saying something about cardinality. When we no longer use the axiom of choice, cardinality becomes a subtle concept. The statement
no longer corresponds to
being “smaller” than
but rather that
is “less complex” than
. This is perhaps analogous to some statistical models which may be “large” but do not overfit due to subtle constraints on the model complexity.
- In light of the previous remark, I would invite you to think about whether the example I gave is truly spookier than non-measurable sets. It might seem to you that it is simply a reasonable consequence of removing the axiom of choice and restricting ourselves to functions we could actually write down or understand. I’ll let you decide
Footnotes
- Technically Solovay proved that there exists a model of set theory such that every subset of
is Borel measurable. To get the result for binary sequences we have to restrict to
and use the binary expansion of
to define a function
. Solvay’s paper is available here https://www.jstor.org/stable/1970696?seq=1